Natural Theology or Evidences of the Existence and Attributes of the Deity
Title Page of first American edition | |
Author | William Paley |
---|---|
Language | English |
Genre | Christian apologetics, philosophy of religion |
Publisher |
R. Faulder, London John Morgan, Philadelphia |
Publication date | 1802 |
Natural Theology or Evidences of the Existence and Attributes of the Deity is an 1802 work of Christian apologetics and philosophy of religion by the English clergyman William Paley (July 1743 – 25 May 1805). The book expounds his arguments from natural theology, making a teleological argument for the existence of God, notably beginning with the watchmaker analogy.
The book was written in the context of the natural theology tradition. In earlier centuries, theologians such as John Ray and William Derham, as well as philosophers of classical times such as Cicero, argued for the existence and goodness of God from the general well-being of living things and the physical world.
Paley's Natural Theology is an extended argument, constructed around a series of examples including finding a watch; comparing the eye to a telescope; and the existence of finely adapted mechanical structures in animals, such as joints which function like hinges or manmade ball and socket joints. Paley argues that these all lead to an intelligent Creator, and that a system is more than the sum of its parts. The last chapters are more theological in character, arguing that the attributes of God must be sufficient for the extent of his operations, and that God must be good because designs seen in nature are beneficial.
The book was many times republished and remains in print. It continues to be consulted by creationists. Charles Darwin took its arguments seriously and responded to them; evolutionary biologists like Stephen Jay Gould and Richard Dawkins continue to discuss Paley's book to respond to modern proponents with similar ideas.
Context
The main thrust of William Paley's argument in Natural Theology is that God's design of the whole creation can be seen in the general happiness, or well-being, that is evident in the physical and social order of things. This sets the book within the broad tradition of the Enlightenment's natural theology; and this explains why Paley based much of his thought on John Ray (1691), William Derham (1711) and Bernard Nieuwentyt (1750).[1]
Paley's argument is built mainly around anatomy and natural history. "For my part", he says, "I take my stand in human anatomy"; elsewhere he insists upon "the necessity, in each particular case, of an intelligent designing mind for the contriving and determining of the forms which organized bodies bear". In making his argument, Paley employed a wide variety of metaphors and analogies.[2] Perhaps the most famous is his analogy between a watch and the world. Historians, philosophers and theologians often call this the watchmaker analogy. Building on this mechanical analogy, Paley presents examples from planetary astronomy and argues that the regular movements of the solar system resemble the workings of a giant clock. To bolster his views he cites the work of his old friend John Law and the Dublin Astronomer Royal John Brinkley.[3]
The germ of the idea is to be found in ancient writers who used sundials and Ptolemaic epicycles to illustrate the divine order of the world. These types of examples can be seen in the work of the ancient philosopher Cicero, especially in his De Natura Deorum, ii. 87 and 97.[4] The watch analogy was widely used in the Enlightenment, by deists and Christians alike.
Outline
- Chapter I. State of the Argument
- The basic watchmaker analogy: if you find a watch, you suppose there's a watchmaker.
- Chapter II. State of the Argument continued
- Now the watch can reproduce itself. Paley argues that the watchmaker must have power, and specific intentions.
- Chapter III. Application of the Argument
- Paley says it is atheism not to agree with the watchmaker argument. He compares the eye to a telescope, and argues from the eye's construction.
- Chapter IV Of the Succession of Plants and Animals
- Paley argues from the properties of plant seeds and animal eggs.
- Chapter V. Application of the Argument continued
- The argument is extended to 'all the organized parts of the works of nature'. Paley considers whether chance alone could explain these, and concludes not.
- Chapter VI. The Argument cumulative
- No argument, writes Paley, other than 'the necessity of an intelligent Creator', can explain the eye (or any other elaborate living structure).
- Chapter VII. Of the Mechanical And Immechanical Parts and Functions of Animals and Vegetables
- Animals use muscles to move; even if we don't understand how they work, we can see they work mechanically, argues Paley, moving joints to and fro. Other organs such as the stomach work chemically to digest food.
- Chapter VIII. Of Mechanical Arrangement in the human Frame
- The bones and joints form a mechanical structure with features comparable to hinges, mortice and tenon and ball and socket joints, etc, to provide both support and suitable flexibility. He compares the spine to The Iron Bridge at Bishop Wearmouth.
- Chapter IX. Of the Muscles
- The muscles exactly relate to the joints, operating them mechanically like the wires and strings of a puppet. A complex case is the tongue. Sphincter muscles are admired also.
- Chapter X. Of the Vessels of Animal Bodies
- The blood vessels and lymph vessels are considered, the valves of the heart, and the separate functions of arteries and veins. Paley argues that such functions as that of the epiglottis could not have formed gradually (as by evolution).
- Chapter XI. Of the Animal Structure regarded as a Mass
- Paley considers the bilateral symmetry of animals, and how well-packaged all the delicate organs are, resulting in both beauty and utility.
- Chapter XII. Comparative Anatomy
- Paley considers the equivalents of human anatomy in other animals. Human clothing is compared to the fur, feathers, quills and scales of animals. The structure of the feather is admired. The teeth and jaws of carnivores, herbivores and omnivores are considered. Similarly, the adaptations of birds' bills in species like the crossbill, spoonbill and (long-billed) snipe are discussed.
- Chapter XIII. Peculiar Organizations
- Paley considers organs which seem to have no comparison, like the oil glands of birds and swim bladders of fishes.
- Chapter XIV. Prospective Contrivances
- Paley considers how some structures are seen to be prepared for future function, like the milk-teeth of a baby, ready formed inside the gums at birth. Similarly, the circulation of the foetus is supported by temporary short-circuits with the foramen ovale and the ductus arteriosus, as the lungs are not yet in use for breathing.
- Chapter XV. Relations
- Paley considers how the whole of a system is more than the sum of its parts. This is seen to be so both in a mechanical watch and in living systems.
- Chapter XVI. Compensation
- The 'defects' of one organ are remedied by the structure of another. The elephant has, Paley argues, a short neck because its head is so heavy, but in compensation it has a long trunk, enabling it to reach out. Similarly the spider has no wings to enable it to chase its flying prey, but has a web, and organs adapted to produce it, which compensates for the lack.
- Chapter XVII. The Relation of animated Bodies to inanimate Nature
- Organs such as the wings of birds and the fins of fish are expressly adapted to the surrounding 'elements' of air or water in which they operate.
- Chapter XVIII. Instincts
- Instincts enable newly-hatched young of salmon to find food, and later to migrate to the sea and finally back to their rivers to spawn.
- Chapter XIX. Of Insects
- "WE are not writing a system of natural history", begins Paley, apologising for not covering every class systematically. He mentions insects for some examples unique to them, as the antennae, elytra (scaly wing-cases), ovipositors (he calls them 'awls') for laying eggs deep in plants or wood, stings, the proboscis of bees, the light-producing organ of the glow-worm and so on.
- Chapter XX. Of Plants
- Admitting that plants generally have less obvious evidence of 'a designed and studied mechanism' than animals, still Paley adds some examples, as of the parts of the seed, the delicate germ being protected by a tough or spiny husk, and dispersed by wings or other appendages.
- Chapter XXI. Of the Elements
- Paley considers how the 'elements' of water, air etc are exactly as needed.
- Chapter XXII. Astronomy
- Paley admits that astronomy is not the best proof of 'the agency of an intelligent Creator', but all the same it shows his magnificence.
- Chapter XXIII. Personality of the Deity
- All the above items show the 'contrivances' in existence, which Paley argues prove the personality of the Deity, arguing that only persons can contrive or design.
- Chapter XXIV. Of the natural Attributes of the Deity
- The attributes of God must, Paley argues, be 'adequate to the magnitude, extent, and multiplicity of his operations'.
- Chapter XXV. Of the Unity of the Deity
- Paley argues that the uniformity of plan seen in the universe indicates a single God.
- Chapter XXVI. The Goodness of the Deity
- God must be good, Paley argues, because in many cases the designs seen in nature are beneficial, and because animals perceive pleasure, beyond what would be strictly necessary. Pain is admitted to exist, but even such things as venomous bites of snakes exist to a good end, namely defence or the capture of prey. Pain too is mitigated, as in intervals between the acute pain of gout which are beneficial to sufferers. The appearance of chance, too, is necessary in the world.
- Chapter XXVII. Conclusion
- Paley concludes that natural theology offers many proofs of the goodness of God, though any one would be sufficient. The many proofs show that the conclusion is stable, and together they can make a suitable impression on those who study them.
Editions
The first edition of Natural Theology: or, Evidences of the Existence and Attributes of the Deity was published in 1802 in London by J. Faulder.[5] In the United States, the book was published and released by E Sargeant and Company of New York on December 15, 1802.[6] A later edition published by E. S. Gorham contained revisions by F. LeGros Clark in order to "harmonize with modern science".[7]
The book was republished in many editions by publishers in cities including London, Oxford, Cambridge, Edinburgh and Philadelphia. The twentieth reprint was made in 1820.[8] Versions appeared in years including 1802, 1807, 1809, 1813, 1818, 1819, 1821, 1823, 1825, 1826, 1829, 1830, 1840, 1854 and many later years. The book remains in print, with more recent editions for example in 2006, 2008, 2009, 2010 and 2014. The book was also republished in editions of Paley's Collected Works. It has been translated into languages including French and Welsh.[7][9]
Opinions on Paley's arguments
Philosophy
The Scottish philosopher David Hume (who died in 1776, before Paley assembled his arguments into Natural Theology) criticised Paley's arguments on several grounds. Firstly, he rejected the making of an analogy between the world and a human artifact such as a watch, since these are so dissimilar that any analogy must be very weak and unreliable. Secondly, Hume argues that even if one accepted the analogy, it would not prove that the creator is infinite, good, or perfectly intelligent,[10] nor that there would be only one creator god. After all, wrote Hume, "what shadow of an argument… can you produce from your hypothesis to prove the unity of the Deity? A great number of men join in building a house or ship, in rearing a city, in framing a commonwealth; why may not several deities combine in contriving and framing a world?"[11]
Contemporary reception
The Edinburgh Review of 1802-3 commented that[12]
With less learning and less originality than some of his distinguished predecessors [such as John Ray and William Derham, who are mentioned], it would be difficult, perhaps, to point out his superior in soundness of judgement, or in vigilant and comprehensive sagacity. With great strength of reasoning and power of decision, he has also united more moderation and liberality of sentiment, than is usually to be found among disputants; and added weight to his argument by a certain plainness and sobriety of manner, that is infinitely better calculated to produce conviction than the sallies of an ambitious eloquence.[12]
The review agreed with Paley that "No thinking man, we conceive, can doubt that there are marks of design in the universe" and that either a single example like the eye would be conclusive, or no quantity of examples would be. Paley is praised for relying on "mechanical phenomena" rather than arguments about human intelligence.[12]
The bible commentator William Jenks described the book in 1838 as "a work highly celebrated for the justness of its reflections, and the benevolence, good sense, and piety which it breathes."[13]
Evolutionary biology
Charles Darwin read Natural Theology during his student years, and later stated in his autobiography that he was initially convinced by the argument:
Although I did not think much about the existence of a personal God until a considerably later period of my life, I will here give the vague conclusions to which I have been driven. The old argument of design in nature, as given by Paley, which formerly seemed to me so conclusive, fails, now that the law of natural selection has been discovered. We can no longer argue that, for instance, the beautiful hinge of a bivalve shell must have been made by an intelligent being, like the hinge of a door by man. There seems to be no more design in the variability of organic beings and in the action of natural selection, than in the course which the wind blows. Everything in nature is the result of fixed laws.— Charles Darwin, The Autobiography of Charles Darwin 1809–1882.[14]
In 1993 the evolutionary biologist Stephen Jay Gould compared Paley to Voltaire's Doctor Pangloss, the man who could argue any case (however hopeless). Gould is struck that Paley can claim that even the agonising pain of gallstones or gout could indicate the goodness of a loving God, with the justification that it felt so good when the pain stopped. Gould makes it clear he finds Paley's argument incorrect scientifically, but states that he respects it as a coherent and well-defended philosophy. Gould particularly respects Paley's method of identifying alternative possibilities and then systematically refuting them. Gould notes that Paley envisages a Lamarckist kind of evolution and rebuts it with the observation that men have not lost their nipples through disuse. However, Gould writes, Paley did not manage to think of one more alternative, natural selection, which has no purpose at all but just kills off whatever works less well in every generation.[15]
The evolutionary biologist Richard Dawkins described himself as a neo-Paleyan in The Blind Watchmaker (1986), where he argued, following the evolutionary biologist and humanist Julian Huxley,[16] that Paley's watch analogy fails to recognise the difference between the complexity of living organisms and that of inanimate objects. Living organisms can reproduce themselves, so they can change to become more complex from generation to generation. Inanimate objects such as watches are unable to pass on any changes, so they never become more complex unless a watchmaker redesigns them. The comparison breaks down, in Dawkins's view, because of this important distinction.[17]
Creationism
The arguments in Paley's book have been rejected by "virtually all biologists".[18] In its place, the theory of evolution has been widely accepted by scientists from Darwin onwards,[19] and Darwin persuaded "most educated people" that processes such as evolution were governed by natural laws.[20] This has not stopped creationists such as those in the Intelligent Design movement from continuing to use Paley's arguments:[18]
Although proponents of ID claim that their premises differ from Paley's, and, unlike Paley, do not specify who or what the designer is, most evolutionary biologists see ID as a version of Paley's arguments updated to account for advances in our understanding of biology."[18]
See also
References
- ↑ Eddy, Matthew Daniel & Knight, David M. (2006). William Paley, Natural Theology. Introduction. Oxford University Press.
- ↑ Eddy, Matthew Daniel (2004). "The Science and Rhetoric of Paley's Natural Theology". Literature and Theology. 18: 1–22. doi:10.1093/litthe/18.1.1.
- ↑ Eddy, Matthew Daniel (2008). Natural Theology. Oxford University Press. pp. Appendix entry on Brinkley.
- ↑ Hallam, Henry (1847). Introduction to the Literature of Europe, Vol II. London: Murray. p. 385.
- ↑ Paley, William (1802), Natural Theology: or, Evidences of the Existence and Attributes of the Deity (1st ed.), London: J. Faulder
- ↑ "(Ad)". The Evening Post (New York, New York). 21 Dec 1802. p. 4. Retrieved 9 November 2014.
- 1 2 "Paley's "Natural Theology."". The Kansas City Times (Kansas City, Missouri). 7 Mar 1911. p. 6. Retrieved 9 November 2014.
- ↑ "Paley, William". Complete Dictionary of Scientific Biography. 2008.
- ↑ "Search results for 'William Paley "Natural Theology or Evidences of the Existence and Attributes of the Deity"'". WorldCat.org. OCLC WorldCat. Retrieved 9 November 2014.
- ↑ Hume, David (1948). "Part II". Dialogues Concerning Natural Religion (with introduction by Norman Kemp Smith ed.). Social Sciences Publishers.
- ↑ Hume, David (1948). "Part V". Dialogues Concerning Natural Religion (with introduction by Norman Kemp Smith ed.). Social Sciences Publishers.
- 1 2 3 Anon. "Art. III. Review of Natural Theology by William Paley". Edinburgh Review. 1: 287–305. Retrieved 9 November 2014.
- ↑ Jenks, William, ed. (1838). "Paley, William, D.D.". The Comprehensive Commentary on the Holy Bible. Fessenden & Company. p. 172.
- ↑ Quoted in The Portable Atheist, edited by Christopher Hitchens, Da Capo Press, 2007. p. 94
- ↑ Gould, Stephen Jay (2007) [1993]. Eight Little Piggies: Reflections in Natural History. Vintage. pp. 142–148.
- ↑ Huxley, Julian (1953). Evolution as Process. Harper and Row. p. 4.
- ↑ Richard Dawkins (1986). The Blind Watchmaker: Why the Evidence of Evolution Reveals a Universe Without Design. W.W. Norton. pp. 43–76. ISBN 978-0-393-31570-7. Retrieved 20 September 2014.
- 1 2 3 Moore, Randy (2009). "William Paley, 1743–1805". Reports of the National Center for Science Education. 29 (4): 26–27.
- ↑ Rafferty, John P (2011). New Thinking about Evolution. Rosen. p. 53.
- ↑ Bowler, Peter J. (2003). Evolution: The History of an Idea. University of California Press. p. 178.
Versions
- Paley, William (1802), Natural Theology: or, Evidences of the Existence and Attributes of the Deity (1st ed.), London: J. Faulder
External links
- William Paley.com
- Berkeley: Paley
- Full text of William Paley's Natural Theology
- University of Sussex: Enlightening Science: Natural Theology and Creationism
- NCSE: William Paley, 1743—1805
- Lander University: William Paley, The Teleological Argument